Lecture 3

Slides available here

Video available here

3.1 Cofibrant Generation

Definition 3.1.1. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be cocomplete category, $S$ a set of morphisms in $\mathcal{C}$, and $I$ any collection of morphisms in $\mathcal{C}$. Then denote by:

Definition 3.1.2. A model category $\mathcal{C}$ is cofibrantly generated if there are small sets of morphisms $I$ and $J$ in $\mathrm{mor}(\mathcal{C})$ such that:

  1. $\mathrm{cof}(I)$ coincides with the collection of cofibrations of $\mathcal{C}$.
  2. $\mathrm{cof}(J)$ coincides with the collection of acyclic cofibrations in $\mathcal{C}$.
  3. The domains of the elements of $I$ and $J$ are small relative to $I$ and $J$ respectively.

In other words, the set $I$ (resp., $J$) generates all cofibrations (resp., acyclic cofibrations) via transfinite constructions.

Lemma 3.1.3 ([Proposition 2.1.18, Hov99]). Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a cofibrantly generated model category then:

  1. $\mathrm{cof(I)} = \mathrm{llp}(\mathrm{rlp}(I))$.
  2. $\mathrm{cof(J)} = \mathrm{llp}(\mathrm{rlp}(J))$.

In particular, the fibrations are exactly the class $\mathrm{rlp}(J)$ and the acyclic fibrations are $\mathrm{rlp}(I)$.

Most model strucutres that we encounter in nature are cofibrantly generated, but this does not mean that there are none. The following model structure on $\textbf{Top}$ is such an example.

Proposition 3.1.4 ([Str72]). There is a model structure on the category $\textbf{Top}$ where a map $f \colon X \to Y$ is a:

We will call this the Strøm model structure and denote it $\textbf{Top}_{\mathrm{Str}}$. All objects in this model structure are bifibrant.

Proposition 3.1.5 ([Remark 4.7, Rap10]). $\textbf{Top}_{\mathrm{Str}}$ is a not a cofibrantly generated model category.

Definition 3.1.6. A category $\mathcal{C}$ is locally presentable if:

  1. The category $\mathcal{C}$ admits all small colimits.
  2. There exists a small set of objects $S$ which generate $\mathcal{C}$ under colimits.
  3. Every object in $\mathcal{C}$ is small.
  4. For any pair of objects $X,Y \in \mathcal{C}$, the object $\mathrm{Hom}(X,Y)$ is a set.

Definition 3.1.7. A model category $\mathcal{C}$ is combinatorial if it is cofibrantly generated and locally presentable.

3.2 Right Transferred Model Structures

We suppose that $\mathcal{C}$ is a model category, and that we have an adjunction

\[ U : \mathcal{D} \leftrightarrows \mathcal{C} : F \]

such that $U$ is the right adjoint to $F$. We do not require that $\mathcal{D}$ have all small limits or colimits.

Definition 3.2.1. The right transferred model structure on $\mathcal{D}$ (if it exists) has $f \colon X \to Y$ a:

Moreover the pair $F,U$ is a Quillen adjunction between these model structures.

Remark 3.2.2.Let $I$ and $J$ be the generating cofibrations and acyclic cofibrations of $\mathcal{C}$ then if the transferred model structure exists then under some mild assumptions (i.e., $F$ preserves small objects) we will see that $\mathcal{C}$ will have generating cofibrations $FI$ and generating acyclic cofibrations $FJ$. We will see in Proposition 3.2.4 that this style of thinking allows us to verify the existence of the model structure in quite a straightforward fashion.

Let us call a morphism in $\mathcal{D}$ an anodyne morphism if it has the LLP with respect to all fibrations. For the model to exist the anodyne morphisms must coincide with the weak equivalences which are also cofibrations.

Theorem 3.2.3 ([Section II, GJ99]). Let $\mathcal{C}$ and $\mathcal{D}$ be as above, then necessary and sufficient conditions for the existence of the right transferred model structure are:

  1. (Factorizations) Every morphism in $\mathcal{D}$ factors as a cofibration followed by an acyclic fibration, and as an anodyne morphism followed by a fibration.
  2. (Acyclicity) Every anodyne morphism is a weak equivalence.

In practice the two above conditions are hard to check. However, we can give more checkable conditions. In particular Proposition 3.2.4 is useful for checking the factorizations while Propositions 3.2.5 and 3.2.6 can be used to verify the acyclicity condition.

Proposition 3.2.4. Suppose that

  1. $\mathcal{C}$ is cofibrantly generated;
  2. $F$ preserves small objects (which follows if $U$ preserves filtered colimits);

then every morphism in $\mathcal{D}$ factors as a cofibration followed by an acyclic fibration, and as an anodyne morphism followed by a fibration. Moreover, if the transferred model structure exists on $\mathcal{D}$ then it is cofibrantly generated. The generating (acyclic) cofibrations are the images under $F$ of the generating (acyclic) cofibrations of $\mathcal{C}$.

Proposition 3.2.5. If a sequential colimit of pushouts of images under $F$ of generating acyclic cofibrations is a weak equivalence in $\mathcal{D}$, then the anodyne morphisms are weak equivalences.

Proposition 3.2.6 ([Section II.4, Qui67]). Let $\mathcal{C}$ and $\mathcal{D}$ as above, moreover suppose that

  1. $\mathcal{D}$ has a fibrant replacement functor (not necessarily functorial);
  2. $\mathcal{D}$ has path objects for fibrant objects;

then the anodyne morphisms are weak equivalences.

Remark 3.2.7.The dual case of left transfer is much more complicated. This is in part due to the lack of fibrantly generated model structure, and the fact that one cannot easily identify a set of generating (acyclic) cofibrations.

3.3 Examples

3.3.1 Functor Categories

Proposition 3.3.2 ([Section 11.6, Hir03]). Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a cofibrantly generated model category, and $\mathcal{D}$ a small category. We define the projective model structure, $\mathcal{C}^\mathcal {D}_\mathrm {proj}$, where a natural transformation $f \colon X \to Y$ is a:

Proposition 3.3.3.There is a model structure on the category of bisimplicial sets $\textbf{ssSet} = \textbf{sSet}^{\Delta ^{op}}$ where a morphism $f \colon X \to Y$ is a:

We call this the (Kan-Quillen) projective model structure on $\textbf{ssSet}$ and denote it $\textbf{ssSet}_\mathrm {proj}$.

3.3.4 The Thomason Model Structure

Proposition 3.3.5 ([Section 3, Tho80]). There is a cofibrantly generated model structure on $\textbf{Cat}$ where a functor $F \colon \mathcal{C} \to \mathcal{D}$ is a:

We call this model structure the Thomason model structure on $\textbf{Cat}$ and denote it $\textbf{Cat}_\mathrm {Thom}$.

Remark 3.3.6.Although we have defined the weak equivalences to be those lifted against $\operatorname {Ex}^2N$, it should be noted that $\operatorname {Ex}^2N(F)$ is a weak equivalence in the Kan-Quillen model structure on $\textbf{sSet}$ if and only if $N$ is as there is a natural weak equivalence $\operatorname {id} \to \operatorname {Ex}^2$ [Lemma 3.7, Ill72]. The key reason we use the two-fold extension is to force the fibrant objects to be what we want.

Proposition 3.3.7 ([Section 3, Tho80]). There is a Quillen equivalence

\[ \tau _1 \operatorname {sd}^2 : \textbf{sSet}_{\mathrm{Kan}} \rightleftarrows \textbf{Cat}_{\mathrm{Thom}} : \operatorname {Ex}^2 N \]

3.4 References for Lecture 3

[GJ99] Paul Goerss and John F. Jardine. Simplicial homotopy theory, volume 174 of Progress in Mathematics. Birkhauser Verlag, Basel,1999.

[Hir03] Philip S. Hirschhorn. Model categories and their localizations, volume 99 of Mathematical Surveys and Monographs. American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI,2003.

[Hov99] Mark Hovey. Model categories, volume 63 of Mathematical Surveys and Monographs. American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI,1999.

[Ill72] Luc Illusie. Complexe cotangent et deformations. II, volume 283 of Lectures Notes in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag, Berlin-New York, 1972.

[Qui67] Daniel G. Quillen. Homotopical Algebra, volume 43 of Lecture Notes in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag, Berlin-New York, 1967.

[Rap10] George Raptis. Homotopy theory of posets. Homology Homotopy Appl., 12(2):211-230, 2010.

[Str72] Arne Strøm. The homotopy category is a homotopy category. Arch. Math., 23:435-441, 1972.

[Tho80] R. W. Thomason. Cat as a closed model category. Cahiers Topologie Geom. Differentielle, 2(3):305-324, 1980.